About CommentOnThis.comThis is a site designed to make it easier to take the core of large published reports and allow anyone to comment on them. More... |
Contents:Islam in English LawCivil and Religious Law in England - lecture by the Archbishop of Canterbury, Dr Rowan Williams
From Lambeth Palace, 7 February 2008
The title of this series of lectures signals the existence of what is very widely felt to be a growing
challenge in our society — that is, the presence of communities which, while no less 'law-abiding'
than the rest of the population, relate to something other than the British legal system alone. But,
as I hope to suggest, the issues that arise around what level of public or legal recognition, if any,
might be allowed to the legal provisions of a religious group, are not peculiar to Islam: we might
recall that, while the law of the Church of England is the law of the land, its daily operation is in
the hands of authorities to whom considerable independence is granted. And beyond the specific
issues that arise in relation to the practicalities of recognition or delegation, there are large
questions in the background about what we understand by and expect from the law, questions
that are more sharply focused than ever in a largely secular social environment. I shall therefore
be concentrating on certain issues around Islamic law to begin with, in order to open up some of
these wider matters.
Among the manifold anxieties that haunt the discussion of the place of Muslims in British society,
one of the strongest, reinforced from time to time by the sensational reporting of opinion polls, is
that Muslim communities in this country seek the freedom to live under sharia law. And what most
people think they know of sharia is that it is repressive towards women and wedded to archaic
and brutal physical punishments; just a few days ago, it was reported that a 'forced marriage'
involving a young woman with learning difficulties had been 'sanctioned under sharia law' — the
kind of story that, in its assumption that we all 'really' know what is involved in the practice of
sharia, powerfully reinforces the image of — at best — a pre-modern system in which human rights
have no role. The problem is freely admitted by Muslim scholars. 'In the West', writes Tariq
Ramadan in his groundbreaking Western Muslims and the Future of Islam, 'the idea of Sharia
calls up all the darkest images of Islam…It has reached the extent that many Muslim intellectuals
do not dare even to refer to the concept for fear of frightening people or arousing suspicion of all
their work by the mere mention of the word' (p.31). Even when some of the more dramatic fears
are set aside, there remains a great deal of uncertainty about what degree of accommodation the
law of the land can and should give to minority communities with their own strongly entrenched
legal and moral codes. As such, this is not only an issue about Islam but about other faith groups,
including Orthodox Judaism; and indeed it spills over into some of the questions which have
surfaced sharply in the last twelve months about the right of religious believers in general to opt
out of certain legal provisions — as in the problems around Roman Catholic adoption agencies
which emerged in relation to the Sexual Orientation Regulations last spring.
Comment: So he's asking for a degree of accomodation of particular groups' own religious or moral code, and clarity about how that accomodation works. Plus he's pointing out that this is already a problem, ie taht ... Reply?.
This lecture will not attempt a detailed discussion of the nature of sharia, which would be far
beyond my competence; my aim is only, as I have said, to tease out some of the broader issues
around the rights of religious groups within a secular state, with a few thought about what might
be entailed in crafting a just and constructive relationship between Islamic law and the statutory
law of the United Kingdom. But it is important to begin by dispelling one or two myths about
sharia; so far from being a monolithic system of detailed enactments, sharia designates primarily
— to quote Ramadan again — 'the expression of the universal principles of Islam [and] the
framework and the thinking that makes for their actualization in human history' (32). Universal
principles: as any Muslim commentator will insist, what is in view is the eternal and absolute will
of God for the universe and for its human inhabitants in particular; but also something that has to
be 'actualized', not a ready-made system. If shar' designates the essence of the revealed Law,
sharia is the practice of actualizing and applying it; while certain elements of the sharia are
specified fairly exactly in the Qur'an and Sunna and in the hadith recognised as authoritative in
this respect, there is no single code that can be identified as 'the' sharia. And when certain states
impose what they refer to as sharia or when certain Muslim activists demand its recognition
alongside secular jurisdictions, they are usually referring not to a universal and fixed code
established once for all but to some particular concretisation of it at the hands of a tradition of
jurists. In the hands of contemporary legal traditionalists, this means simply that the application of
sharia must be governed by the judgements of representatives of the classical schools of legal
interpretation. But there are a good many voices arguing for an extension of the liberty of ijtihad —
basically reasoning from first principles rather than simply the collation of traditional judgements
(see for example Louis Gardet, 'Un prealable aux questions soulevees par les droits de l'homme:
l'actualisation de la Loi religieuse musulmane aujourd'hui', Islamochristiana 9, 1983, 1-12, and
Abdullah Saeed, 'Trends in Contemporary Islam: a Preliminary Attempt at a Classification', The
Muslim World, 97:3, 2007, 395-404, esp. 401-2).
Thus, in contrast to what is sometimes assumed, we do not simply have a standoff between two
rival legal systems when we discuss Islamic and British law. On the one hand, sharia depends for
its legitimacy not on any human decision, not on votes or preferences, but on the conviction that it
represents the mind of God; on the other, it is to some extent unfinished business so far as
codified and precise provisions are concerned. To recognise sharia is to recognise a method of
jurisprudence governed by revealed texts rather than a single system. In a discussion based on a
paper from Mona Siddiqui at a conference last year at Al Akhawayn University in Morocco, the
point was made by one or two Muslim scholars that an excessively narrow understanding sharia
as simply codified rules can have the effect of actually undermining the universal claims of the
Qur'an.
But while such universal claims are not open for renegotiation, they also assume the voluntary
consent or submission of the believer, the free decision to be and to continue a member of the
umma. Sharia is not, in that sense, intrinsically to do with any demand for Muslim dominance over
non-Muslims. Both historically and in the contemporary context, Muslim states have
acknowledged that membership of the umma is not coterminous with membership in a particular
political society: in modern times, the clearest articulation of this was in the foundation of the
Pakistani state under Jinnah; but other examples (Morocco, Jordan) could be cited of societies
where there is a concept of citizenship that is not identical with belonging to the umma. Such
societies, while not compromising or weakening the possibility of unqualified belief in the authority
and universality of sharia, or even the privileged status of Islam in a nation, recognise that there
can be no guarantee that the state is religiously homogeneous and that the relationships in which
the individual stands and which define him or her are not exclusively with other Muslims. There
has therefore to be some concept of common good that is not prescribed solely in terms of
revealed Law, however provisional or imperfect such a situation is thought to be. And this implies
in turn that the Muslim, even in a predominantly Muslim state, has something of a dual identity, as
citizen and as believer within the community of the faithful.
It is true that this account would be hotly contested by some committed Islamic primitivists, by
followers of Sayyid Qutb and similar polemicists; but it is fair to say that the great body of serious
jurists in the Islamic world would recognise this degree of political plurality as consistent with
Muslim integrity. In this sense, while (as I have said) we are not talking about two rival systems
on the same level, there is some community of understanding between Islamic social thinking and
the categories we might turn to in the non-Muslim world for the understanding of law in the most
general context. There is a recognition that our social identities are not constituted by one
exclusive set of relations or mode of belonging — even if one of those sets is regarded as relating
to the most fundamental and non-negotiable level of reality, as established by a 'covenant'
between the divine and the human (as in Jewish and Christian thinking; once again, we are not
talking about an exclusively Muslim problem). The danger arises not only when there is an
assumption on the religious side that membership of the community (belonging to the umma or
the Church or whatever) is the only significant category, so that participation in other kinds of
socio-political arrangement is a kind of betrayal. It also occurs when secular government
assumes a monopoly in terms of defining public and political identity. There is a position — not at
all unfamiliar in contemporary discussion — which says that to be a citizen is essentially and
simply to be under the rule of the uniform law of a sovereign state, in such a way that any other
relations, commitments or protocols of behaviour belong exclusively to the realm of the private
and of individual choice. As I have maintained in several other contexts, this is a very
unsatisfactory account of political reality in modern societies; but it is also a problematic basis for
thinking of the legal category of citizenship and the nature of human interdependence. Maleiha
Malik, following Alasdair MacIntyre, argues in an essay on 'Faith and the State of Jurisprudence'
(Faith in Law: Essays in Legal Theory, ed. Peter Oliver, Sionaidh Douglas Scott and Victor
Tadros, 2000, pp.129-49) that there is a risk of assuming that 'mainstreram' jurisprudence should
routinely and unquestioningly bypass the variety of ways in which actions are as a matter of fact
understood by agents in the light of the diverse sorts of communal belonging they are involved in.
If that is the assumption, 'the appropriate temporal unit for analysis tends to be the basic action.
Instead of concentrating on the history of the individual or the origins of the social practice which
provides the context within which the act is performed, conduct tends to be studied as an isolated
and one-off act' (139-40). And another essay in the same collection, Anthony Bradney's 'Faced
by Faith' (89-105) offers some examples of legal rulings which have disregarded the account
offered by religious believers of the motives for their own decisions, on the grounds that the court
alone is competent to assess the coherence or even sincerity of their claims. And when courts
attempt to do this on the grounds of what is 'generally acceptable' behaviour in a society, they are
open, Bradney claims (102-3) to the accusation of undermining the principle of liberal pluralism by
denying someone the right to speak in their own voice. The distinguished ecclesiastical lawyer,
Chancellor Mark Hill, has also underlined in a number of recent papers the degree of confusion
that has bedevilled recent essays in adjudicating disputes with a religious element, stressing the
need for better definition of the kind of protection for religious conscience that the law intends
(see particularly his essay with Russell Sandberg, 'Is Nothing Sacred? Clashing Symbols in a
Secular World', Public Law 3, 2007, pp.488-506).
I have argued recently in a discussion of the moral background to legislation about incitement to
religious hatred that any crime involving religious offence has to be thought about in terms of its
tendency to create or reinforce a position in which a religious person or group could be gravely
disadvantaged in regard to access to speaking in public in their own right: offence needs to be
connected to issues of power and status, so that a powerful individual or group making
derogatory or defamatory statements about a disadvantaged minority might be thought to be
increasing that disadvantage. The point I am making here is similar. If the law of the land takes no
account of what might be for certain agents a proper rationale for behaviour — for protest against
certain unforeseen professional requirements, for instance, which would compromise religious
discipline or belief — it fails in a significant way to communicate with someone involved in the legal
process (or indeed to receive their communication), and so, on at least one kind of legal theory
(expounded recently, for example, by R.A. Duff), fails in one of its purposes.
The implications are twofold. There is a plain procedural question — and neither Bradney nor
Malik goes much beyond this — about how existing courts function and what weight is properly
give to the issues we have been discussing. But there is a larger theoretical and practical issue
about what it is to live under more than one jurisdiction., which takes us back to the question we
began with — the role of sharia (or indeed Orthodox Jewish practice) in relation to the routine
jurisdiction of the British courts. In general, when there is a robust affirmation that the law of the
land should protect individuals on the grounds of their corporate religious identity and secure their
freedom to fulfil religious duties, a number of queries are regularly raised. I want to look at three
such difficulties briefly. They relate both to the question of whether there should be a higher level
of attention to religious identity and communal rights in the practice of the law, and to the larger
issue I mentioned of something like a delegation of certain legal functions to the religious courts
of a community; and this latter question, it should be remembered, is relevant not only to Islamic
law but also to areas of Orthodox Jewish practice.
The first objection to a higher level of public legal regard being paid to communal identity is that it
leaves legal process (including ordinary disciplinary process within organisations) at the mercy of
what might be called vexatious appeals to religious scruple. A recent example might be the
reported refusal of a Muslim woman employed by Marks and Spencer to handle a book of Bible
stories. Or we might think of the rather more serious cluster of questions around forced
marriages, where again it is crucial to distinguish between cultural and strictly religious
dimensions. While Bradney rightly cautions against the simple dismissal of alleged scruple by
judicial authorities who have made no attempt to understand its workings in the construction of
people's social identities, it should be clear also that any recognition of the need for such
sensitivity must also have a recognised means of deciding the relative seriousness of
conscience-related claims, a way of distinguishing purely cultural habits from seriously-rooted
matters of faith and discipline, and distinguishing uninformed prejudice from religious prescription.
There needs to be access to recognised authority acting for a religious group: there is already, of
course, an Islamic Shari'a Council, much in demand for rulings on marital questions in the UK;
and if we were to see more latitude given in law to rights and scruples rooted in religious identity,
we should need a much enhanced and quite sophisticated version of such a body, with increased
resource and a high degree of community recognition, so that 'vexatious' claims could be
summarily dealt with. The secular lawyer needs to know where the potential conflict is real, legally
and religiously serious, and where it is grounded in either nuisance or ignorance. There can be no
blank cheques given to unexamined scruples.
Comment: The Archbishop wants to distinguish between uninformed prejudice, cultural habits, and religious scruples. He suggests that the last of these should have a status in law which the other two do not, and ... Reply?.
The second issue, a very serious one, is that recognition of 'supplementary jurisdiction' in some
areas, especially family law, could have the effect of reinforcing in minority communities some of
the most repressive or retrograde elements in them, with particularly serious consequences for
the role and liberties of women. The 'forced marriage' question is the one most often referred to
here, and it is at the moment undoubtedly a very serious and scandalous one; but precisely
because it has to do with custom and culture rather than directly binding enactments by religious
authority, I shall refer to another issue. It is argued that the provision for the inheritance of widows
under a strict application of sharia has the effect of disadvantaging them in what the majority
community might regard as unacceptable ways. A legal (in fact Qur'anic) provision which in its
time served very clearly to secure a widow's position at a time when this was practically unknown
in the culture becomes, if taken absolutely literally, a generator of relative insecurity in a new
context (see, for example, Ann Elizabeth Mayer, Islam and Human Rights. Tradition and Politics,
1999, p.111). The problem here is that recognising the authority of a communal religious court to
decide finally and authoritatively about such a question would in effect not merely allow an
additional layer of legal routes for resolving conflicts and ordering behaviour but would actually
deprive members of the minority community of rights and liberties that they were entitled to enjoy
as citizens; and while a legal system might properly admit structures or protocols that embody the
diversity of moral reasoning in a plural society by allowing scope for a minority group to
administer its affairs according to its own convictions, it can hardly admit or 'license' protocols that
effectively take away the rights it acknowledges as generally valid.
To put the question like that is already to see where an answer might lie, though it is not an
answer that will remove the possibility of some conflict. If any kind of plural jurisdiction is
recognised, it would presumably have to be under the rubric that no 'supplementary' jurisdiction
could have the power to deny access to the rights granted to other citizens or to punish its
members for claiming those rights. This is in effect to mirror what a minority might themselves be
requesting — that the situation should not arise where membership of one group restricted the
freedom to live also as a member of an overlapping group, that (in this case) citizenship in a
secular society should not necessitate the abandoning of religious discipline, any more than
religious discipline should deprive one of access to liberties secured by the law of the land, to the
common benefits of secular citizenship — or, better, to recognise that citizenship itself is a
complex phenomenon not bound up with any one level of communal belonging but involving them
all.
But this does not guarantee an absence of conflict. In the particular case we have mentioned, the
inheritance rights of widows, it is already true that some Islamic societies have themselves
proved flexible (Malaysia is a case in point). But let us take a more neuralgic matter still: what
about the historic Islamic prohibition against apostasy, and the draconian penalties entailed? In a
society where freedom of religion is secured by law, it is obviously impossible for any group to
claim that conversion to another faith is simply disallowed or to claim the right to inflict
punishment on a convert. We touch here on one of the most sensitive areas not only in thinking
about legal practice but also in interfaith relations. A significant number of contemporary Islamic
jurists and scholars would say that the Qur'anic pronouncements on apostasy which have been
regarded as the ground for extreme penalties reflect a situation in which abandoning Islam was
equivalent to adopting an active stance of violent hostility to the community, so that extreme
penalties could be compared to provisions in other jurisdictions for punishing spies or traitors in
wartime; but that this cannot be regarded as bearing on the conditions now existing in the world.
Of course such a reading is wholly unacceptable to 'primitivists' in Islam, for whom this would be
an example of a rationalising strategy, a style of interpretation (ijtihad) uncontrolled by proper
traditional norms. But, to use again the terminology suggested a moment ago, as soon as it is
granted that — even in a dominantly Islamic society — citizens have more than one set of defining
relationships under the law of the state, it becomes hard to justify enactments that take it for
granted that the only mode of contact between these sets of relationships is open enmity; in
which case, the appropriateness of extreme penalties for conversion is not obvious even within a
fairly strict Muslim frame of reference. Conversely, where the dominant legal culture is non-
Islamic, but there is a level of serious recognition of the corporate reality and rights of the umma,
there can be no assumption that outside the umma the goal of any other jurisdiction is its
destruction. Once again, there has to be a recognition that difference of conviction is not
automatically a lethal threat.
As I have said, this is a delicate and complex matter involving what is mostly a fairly muted but
nonetheless real debate among Muslim scholars in various contexts. I mention it partly because
of its gravity as an issue in interfaith relations and in discussions of human rights and the
treatment of minorities, partly to illustrate how the recognition of what I have been calling
membership in different but overlapping sets of social relationship (what others have called
'multiple affiliations') can provide a framework for thinking about these neuralgic questions of the
status of women and converts. Recognising a supplementary jurisdiction cannot mean
recognising a liberty to exert a sort of local monopoly in some areas. The Jewish legal theorist
Ayelet Shachar, in a highly original and significant monograph on Multicultural Jurisdictions:
Cultural Differences and Women's Rights (2001), explores the risks of any model that ends up
'franchising' a non-state jurisdiction so as to reinforce its most problematic features and further
disadvantage its weakest members: 'we must be alert', she writes, 'to the potentially injurious
effects of well-meaning external protections upon different categories of group members here —
effects which may unwittingly exacerbate preexisting internal power hierarchies' (113). She
argues that if we are serious in trying to move away from a model that treats one jurisdiction as
having a monopoly of socially defining roles and relations, we do not solve any problems by a
purely uncritical endorsement of a communal legal structure which can only be avoided by
deciding to leave the community altogether. We need, according to Shachar, to 'work to
overcome the ultimatum of 'either your culture or your rights'' (114).
So the second objection to an increased legal recognition of communal religious identities can be
met if we are prepared to think about the basic ground rules that might organise the relationship
between jurisdictions, making sure that we do not collude with unexamined systems that have
oppressive effect or allow shared public liberties to be decisively taken away by a supplementary
jurisdiction. Once again, there are no blank cheques. I shall return to some of the details of
Shachar's positive proposal; but I want to move on to the third objection, which grows precisely
out of the complexities of clarifying the relations between jurisdictions. Is it not both theoretically
and practically mistaken to qualify our commitment to legal monopoly? So much of our thinking in
the modern world, dominated by European assumptions about universal rights, rests, surely, on
the basis that the law is the law; that everyone stands before the public tribunal on exactly equal
terms, so that recognition of corporate identities or, more seriously, of supplementary jurisdictions
is simply incoherent if we want to preserve the great political and social advances of Western
legality.
There is a bit of a risk here in the way we sometimes talk about the universal vision of post-
Enlightenment politics. The great protest of the Enlightenment was against authority that
appealed only to tradition and refused to justify itself by other criteria — by open reasoned
argument or by standards of successful provision of goods and liberties for the greatest number.
Its claim to override traditional forms of governance and custom by looking towards a universal
tribunal was entirely intelligible against the background of despotism and uncritical inherited
privilege which prevailed in so much of early modern Europe. The most positive aspect of this
moment in our cultural history was its focus on equal levels of accountability for all and equal
levels of access for all to legal process. In this respect, it was in fact largely the foregrounding and
confirming of what was already encoded in longstanding legal tradition, Roman and mediaeval,
which had consistently affirmed the universality and primacy of law (even over the person of the
monarch). But this set of considerations alone is not adequate to deal with the realities of
complex societies: it is not enough to say that citizenship as an abstract form of equal access and
equal accountability is either the basis or the entirety of social identity and personal motivation.
Where this has been enforced, it has proved a weak vehicle for the life of a society and has often
brought violent injustice in its wake (think of the various attempts to reduce citizenship to rational
equality in the France of the 1790's or the China of the 1970's). Societies that are in fact
ethnically, culturally and religiously diverse are societies in which identity is formed, as we have
noted by different modes and contexts of belonging, 'multiple affiliation'. The danger is in acting
as if the authority that managed the abstract level of equal citizenship represented a sovereign
order which then allowed other levels to exist. But if the reality of society is plural — as many
political theorists have pointed out — this is a damagingly inadequate account of common life, in
which certain kinds of affiliation are marginalised or privatised to the extent that what is produced
is a ghettoised pattern of social life, in which particular sorts of interest and of reasoning are
tolerated as private matters but never granted legitimacy in public as part of a continuing debate
about shared goods and priorities.
But this means that we have to think a little harder about the role and rule of law in a plural
society of overlapping identities. Perhaps it helps to see the universalist vision of law as
guaranteeing equal accountability and access primarily in a negative rather than a positive sense
— that is, to see it as a mechanism whereby any human participant in a society is protected
against the loss of certain elementary liberties of self-determination and guaranteed the freedom
to demand reasons for any actions on the part of others for actions and policies that infringe self-
determination. This is a slightly more gentle or tactful way of expressing what some legal theorists
will describe as the 'monopoly of legitimate violence' by the law of a state, the absolute restriction
of powers of forcible restraint to those who administer statutory law. This is not to reduce society
itself primarily to an uneasy alliance of self-determining individuals arguing about the degree to
which their freedom is limited by one another and needing forcible restraint in a war of all against
all — though that is increasingly the model which a narrowly rights-based culture fosters,
producing a manically litigious atmosphere and a conviction of the inadequacy of customary
ethical restraints and traditions — of what was once called 'civility'. The picture will not be
unfamiliar, and there is a modern legal culture which loves to have it so. But the point of defining
legal universalism as a negative thing is that it allows us to assume, as I think we should, that the
important springs of moral vision in a society will be in those areas which a systematic abstract
universalism regards as 'private' — in religion above all, but also in custom and habit. The role of
'secular' law is not the dissolution of these things in the name of universalism but the monitoring
of such affiliations to prevent the creation of mutually isolated communities in which human
liberties are seen in incompatible ways and individual persons are subjected to restraints or
injustices for which there is no public redress.
The rule of law is thus not the enshrining of priority for the universal/abstract dimension of social
existence but the establishing of a space accessible to everyone in which it is possible to affirm
and defend a commitment to human dignity as such, independent of membership in any specific
human community or tradition, so that when specific communities or traditions are in danger of
claiming finality for their own boundaries of practice and understanding, they are reminded that
they have to come to terms with the actuality of human diversity - and that the only way of doing
this is to acknowledge the category of 'human dignity as such' — a non-negotiable assumption
that each agent (with his or her historical and social affiliations) could be expected to have a voice
in the shaping of some common project for the well-being and order of a human group. It is not to
claim that specific community understandings are 'superseded' by this universal principle, rather
to claim that they all need to be undergirded by it. The rule of law is — and this may sound rather
counterintuitive — a way of honouring what in the human constitution is not captured by any one
form of corporate belonging or any particular history, even though the human constitution never
exists without those other determinations. Our need, as Raymond Plant has well expressed it, is
for the construction of 'a moral framework which could expand outside the boundaries of
particular narratives while, at the same time, respecting the narratives as the cultural contexts in
which the language [of common dignity and mutually intelligible commitments to work for certain
common moral priorities] is learned and taught' (Politics, Theology and History, 2001, pp.357-8).
I'd add in passing that this is arguably a place where more reflection is needed about the theology
of law; if my analysis is right, the sort of foundation I have sketched for a universal principle of
legal right requires both a certain valuation of the human as such and a conviction that the human
subject is always endowed with some degree of freedom over against any and every actual
system of human social life; both of these things are historically rooted in Christian theology, even
when they have acquired a life of their own in isolation from that theology. It never does any harm
to be reminded that without certain themes consistently and strongly emphasised by the
'Abrahamic' faiths, themes to do with the unconditional possibility for every human subject to live
in conscious relation with God and in free and constructive collaboration with others, there is no
guarantee that a 'universalist' account of human dignity would ever have seemed plausible or
even emerged with clarity. Slave societies and assumptions about innate racial superiority are as
widespread a feature as any in human history (and they have persistently infected even
Abrahamic communities, which is perhaps why the Enlightenment was a necessary wake-up call
to religion…).
But to return to our main theme: I have been arguing that a defence of an unqualified secular
legal monopoly in terms of the need for a universalist doctrine of human right or dignity is to
misunderstand the circumstances in which that doctrine emerged, and that the essential liberating
(and religiously informed) vision it represents is not imperilled by a loosening of the monopolistic
framework. At the moment, as I mentioned at the beginning of this lecture, one of the most
frequently noted problems in the law in this area is the reluctance of a dominant rights-based
philosophy to acknowledge the liberty of conscientious opting-out from collaboration in
procedures or practices that are in tension with the demands of particular religious groups: the
assumption, in rather misleading shorthand, that if a right or liberty is granted there is a
corresponding duty upon every individual to 'activate' this whenever called upon. Earlier on, I
proposed that the criterion for recognising and collaborating with communal religious discipline
should be connected with whether a communal jurisdiction actively interfered with liberties
guaranteed by the wider society in such a way as definitively to block access to the exercise of
those liberties; clearly the refusal of a religious believer to act upon the legal recognition of a right
is not, given the plural character of society, a denial to anyone inside or outside the community of
access to that right. The point has been granted in respect of medical professionals who may be
asked to perform or co-operate in performing abortions — a perfectly reasonable example of the
law doing what I earlier defined as its job, securing space for those aspects of human motivation
and behaviour that cannot be finally determined by any corporate or social system. It is difficult to
see quite why the principle cannot be extended in other areas. But it is undeniable that there is
pressure from some quarters to insist that conscientious disagreement should always be
overruled by a monopolistic understanding of jurisdiction.
I labour the point because what at first seems to be a somewhat narrow point about how Islamic
law and Islamic identity should or might be regarded in our legal system in fact opens up a very
wide range of current issues, and requires some general thinking about the character of law. It
would be a pity if the immense advances in the recognition of human rights led, because of a
misconception about legal universality, to a situation where a person was defined primarily as the
possessor of a set of abstract liberties and the law's function was accordingly seen as nothing but
the securing of those liberties irrespective of the custom and conscience of those groups which
concretely compose a plural modern society. Certainly, no-one is likely to suppose that a scheme
allowing for supplementary jurisdiction will be simple, and the history of experiments in this
direction amply illustrates the problems. But if one approaches it along the lines sketched by
Shachar in the monograph quoted earlier, it might be possible to think in terms of what she calls
'transformative accommodation': a scheme in which individuals retain the liberty to choose the
jurisdiction under which they will seek to resolve certain carefully specified matters, so that
'power-holders are forced to compete for the loyalty of their shared constituents' (122). This may
include aspects of marital law, the regulation of financial transactions and authorised structures of
mediation and conflict resolution — the main areas that have been in question where
supplementary jurisdictions have been tried, with native American communities in Canada as well
as with religious groups like Islamic minority communities in certain contexts. In such schemes,
both jurisdictional stakeholders may need to examine the way they operate; a communal/religious
nomos, to borrow Shachar's vocabulary, has to think through the risks of alienating its people by
inflexible or over-restrictive applications of traditional law, and a universalist Enlightenment
system has to weigh the possible consequences of ghettoising and effectively disenfranchising a
minority, at real cost to overall social cohesion and creativity. Hence 'transformative
accommodation': both jurisdictional parties may be changed by their encounter over time, and we
avoid the sterility of mutually exclusive monopolies.
It is uncomfortably true that this introduces into our thinking about law what some would see as a
'market' element, a competition for loyalty as Shachar admits. But if what we want socially is a
pattern of relations in which a plurality of divers and overlapping affiliations work for a common
good, and in which groups of serious and profound conviction are not systematically faced with
the stark alternatives of cultural loyalty or state loyalty, it seems unavoidable. In other settings, I
have spoken about the idea of 'interactive pluralism' as a political desideratum; this seems to be
one manifestation of such an ideal, comparable to the arrangements that allow for shared
responsibility in education: the best argument for faith schools from the point of view of any
aspiration towards social harmony and understanding is that they bring communal loyalties into
direct relation with the wider society and inevitably lead to mutual questioning and sometimes
mutual influence towards change, without compromising the distinctiveness of the essential
elements of those communal loyalties.
In conclusion, it seems that if we are to think intelligently about the relations between Islam and
British law, we need a fair amount of 'deconstruction' of crude oppositions and mythologies,
whether of the nature of sharia or the nature of the Enlightenment. But as I have hinted, I do not
believe this can be done without some thinking also about the very nature of law. It is always
easy to take refuge in some form of positivism; and what I have called legal universalism, when
divorced from a serious theoretical (and, I would argue, religious) underpinning, can turn into a
positivism as sterile as any other variety. If the paradoxical idea which I have sketched is true —
that universal law and universal right are a way of recognising what is least fathomable and
controllable in the human subject — theology still waits for us around the corner of these debates,
however hard our culture may try to keep it out. And, as you can imagine, I am not going to
complain about that.
Comment: I find I fundamentally agree with what he says, and also with how he expresses it. I can see the incensed reaction to how his comments have been reported. I dont see what in this speech as he wrote it ... Reply?.
Other links |